0079B CAPUT PRIMUM. De sapientia divina et humana.
CAPUT II. De veritate, deque ejus gradibus, atque de Deo.
CAPUT III. De bonis et malis in rebus humanis, eorumque auctore.
CAPUT IV. 0085B De Deo, deque ejus affectibus, Epicurique reprehensione.
CAPUT V. De Deo stoicorum sententia de Ira et gratia ejus.
CAPUT VI. Quod Deus irascatur.
0092B CAPUT VII. De Homine et Brutis, ac Religione.
0096A CAPUT VIII. De religione.
CAPUT IX. De providentia Dei, deque sententiis illi repugnantibus.
CAPUT X. 0100A De Mundi ortu et rerum natura, et Dei providentia.
CAPUT XI. De Deo, eoque uno, cujusque providentia mundus regatur et constat.
0114A CAPUT XII. De religione et Dei timore.
CAPUT XIII De mundi et temporum commodo et usu.
0122A CAPUT XIV. Cur Deus fecerit hominem.
CAPUT XV. Unde ad hominem peccata pervenerint.
0124C CAPUT XVI. De Deo ejusque ira et affectibus.
CAPUT XVII. De Deo, cura et ira.
CAPUT XVIII. De peccatis vindicandis, sine ira fieri non posse.
CAPUT XIX. De anima et corpore, deque Providentia.
CAPUT XX. De peccatis et Dei misericordia.
CAPUT XXI. De ira Dei et hominis.
CAPUT XXII. De peccatis, deque iis recitati versus Sibyllae.
When the philosophers of former times had agreed in their opinions respecting providence, and there was no doubt but that the world was set in order by God and reason, and was governed by reason, Protagoras, in the times of Socrates, was the first of all who said that it was not clear to him whether there was any divinity or not. And this disputation of his was judged so impious, and so contrary to the truth and to religion, that the Athenians both banished him from their territories, and burnt in a public assembly those books of his in which these statements were contained. But there is no need to speak respecting his opinions, because he pronounced nothing certain. After these things Socrates and his disciple Plato, and those who flowed forth from the school of Plato like rivulets into different directions, namely, the Stoics and Peripatetics, were of the same opinion as those who went before them.35 [A beautiful formula of the history of Greek philosophy.]
Afterwards Epicurus said that there was indeed a God, because it was necessary that there should be in the world some being of surpassing excellence, distinction, and blessedness; yet that there was no providence, and thus that the world itself was ordered by no plan, nor art, nor workmanship, but that the universe was made up of certain minute and indivisible seeds. But I do not see what can be said more repugnant to the truth. For if there is a God, as God He is manifestly provident; nor can divinity be attributed to Him in any other way than if He retains the past, and knows the present, and foresees the future. Therefore, in taking away providence, he also denied the existence of God. But when he openly acknowledged the existence of God, at the same time he also admitted His providence for the one cannot exist at all, or be understood, without the other. But in those later times in which philosophy had now lost its vigour 36 Defloruerat. there lived a certain Diagoras of Melos,37 [Vol. vi. p. 421.] who altogether denied the existence of God, and on account of this sentiment was called atheist;38 ἅθεος. also Theodorus39 [Vol. vi. p. 421.] of Cyrene: both of whom, because they were unable to discover anything new, all things having already been said and found out, preferred even, in opposition to the truth, to deny that in which all preceding philosophers had agreed without any ambiguity. These are they who attacked providence, which had been asserted and defended through so many ages by so many intellects. What then? Shall we refute those trifling and inactive philosophers by reason, or by the authority of distinguished men, or rather by both? But we must hasten onwards, lest our speech should wander too far from our subject.
CAPUT IX. De providentia Dei, deque sententiis illi repugnantibus.
Cum sententiae philosophorum prioris temporis de providentia consensissent, nec ulla esset dubitatio, quin mundus a Deo, et ratione esset instructus, et ratione regeretur: primus omnium Protagoras extitit temporibus Socratis, qui sibi diceret non liquere, utrum esset aliqua divinitas, necne. Quae disputatio ejus adeo impia, et contra veritatem et religionem judicata est, ut et ipsum Athenienses expulerint suis finibus, et libros ejus in concione, quibus haec continebantur, exusserint. De cujus sententia non est opus 0098B disputare, quia nihil certi pronuntiavit. Post haec Socrates, et auditor ejus Plato, et qui de schola Platonis, tanquam rivuli diversas in partes profluxerunt; stoici et peripatetici, in eadem fuere sententia, qua priores.
Postea vero Epicurus Deum quidem esse dixit, quia necesse sit esse aliquid in mundo praestans, et eximium, et beatum; providentiam tamen nullam: itaque mundum ipsum nec ratione ulla, nec arte, nec fabrica instructum, sed naturam rerum quibusdam minutis seminibus et insecabilibus conglobatam. Quo quid repugnantius dici possit, non video. Etenim si est Deus, utique providens est, ut Deus; nec aliter ei 0098C potest divinitas attribui, nisi et praeterita teneat, et 0099A praesentia sciat, et futura prospiciat. Cum igitur providentiam sustulit, etiam Deum negavit esse. Cum autem Deum esse professus est, et providentiam simul esse concessit. Alterum enim sine altero nec esse prorsus, nec intelligi potest. Verum iis postea temporibus, quibus jam philosophia defloruerat, extitit Melius quidam Diagoras, qui nullum esse omnino Deum diceret, ob eamque sententiam nominatus est ἄθεος; item Cyrenaeus Theodorus: ambo quia nihil novi poterant reperire, omnibus jam dictis et inventis, maluerunt vel contra veritatem id negare, in quo priores universi sine ambiguitate consenserant. Ii sunt, qui tot saeculis, tot ingeniis assertam atque defensam providentiam calumniati sunt. Quid ergo? utrumne istos minutos et inertes philosophos ratione, an vero auctoritate praestantium virorum refellemus? an potius 0099B utroque? Sed properandum est, ne longius a materia divagetur oratio.