He says, “The Life that is the same, and thoroughly single, must have one and the same outward expression for it, even though in mere names, and manner, and order it may seem to vary. For true expressions derive their precision from the subject realities which they indicate; different expressions are applied to different realities, the same to the same; and so one or other of these two things must of necessity be held; either that the reality indicated is quite different (if the expressions are), or else that the indicating expressions are not different;” and there is in this case no other subject reality besides the life of the Son, “for one either to rest an idea upon, or to cast a different expression upon.” Is there, I may ask, any unfitness in the words quoted, which would prevent them being rightly spoken or written about the Only-begotten? Is not the Son Himself also a “Life thoroughly single”? Is there not for Him also “one and the same” befitting “expression,” “though in mere names, and manner, and order He may seem to vary”? Must not, for Him also, “one or other of these two things be held” fixed, “either that the reality indicated is quite different, or else that the indicating expressions are not different,” there being no other subject reality, besides his life, “for one either to rest an idea upon, or to cast a different expression upon”? We mix up nothing here with what Eunomius has said about the Father; we have only passed from the same accepted premise to the same conclusion as he did, merely inserting the Son’s name instead. If, then, the Son too is a single life, unadulterated, removed from every sort of compositeness or complication, and there is no subject reality besides this life of the Son (for how in that which is simple can the mixture of anything foreign be suspected? what we have to think of along with something else is no longer simple), and if the Father’s substance also is a single life, and of this single life, by virtue of its very life and its very singleness, there are no differences, no increase or decrease in quantity or quality in it creating any variation, it needs must be that things thus coinciding in idea should be called by the same appellation also. If, that is, the thing that is detected both in the Father and the Son, I mean the singleness of life, is one, the very idea of singleness excluding, as we have said, any variation, it needs must be that the name befitting the one should be attached to the other also. For as that which reasons, and is mortal, and is capable of thought and knowledge, is called “man” equally in the case of Adam and of Abel, and this name of the nature is not altered either by the fact that Abel passed into existence by generation, or by the fact that Adam did so without generation, so, if the simplicity129 Reading εἴπερ τὸ ἁπλοῦν with the editt., which is manifestly required by the sense. and incompositeness of the Father’s life has ungeneracy for its name, in like manner for the Son’s life the same idea will necessarily have to be attached to the same utterance, if, as Eunomius says, “one or other of these two things must of necessity be held; either that the reality indicated is quite different, or else that the indicating expressions are not different.”
« Δεῖ », φησί, « τῆς αὐτῆς ζωῆς καὶ τῆς εἰλικρινῶς μιᾶς ἕνα καὶ τὸν αὐτὸν εἶναι λόγον, κἂν τοῖς ὀνόμασι καὶ τῷ τρόπῳ καὶ τῇ τάξει φαίνηται διάφορος: τῶν γὰρ ἀληθῶν λόγων ἐκ τῶν ὑποκειμένων καὶ δηλουμένων πραγμάτων λαμβανόντων τὴν ἐπίκρισιν καὶ τῶν ἑτέρων ἑτέροις πράγμασι συναρμοζομένων, ὥσπερ αὖ καὶ τῶν αὐτῶν τοῖς αὐτοῖς, ἐξ ἀνάγκης δεῖν δυοῖν εἶναι θάτερον, ἢ καὶ τὸ πρᾶγμα τὸ δηλούμενον πάντως ἕτερον ἢ μηδὲ τὸν δηλοῦντα λόγον ἕτερον, μηδενὸς ὑποκειμένου πράγματος παρὰ τὴν » τοῦ υἱοῦ « ζωήν, ᾧ τις ἂν ἢ τὴν διάνοιαν ἐπερείσειεν ἢ τὸν ἕτερον λόγον ἐπιρρίψειε ». μή τίς ἐστιν ἐν τοῖς εἰρημένοις ἀναρμοστία, ὡς οὐ δέον ἐπὶ τοῦ μονογενοῦς τὰ τοιαῦτα λέγειν ἢ γράφειν; οὐχὶ καὶ ὁ υἱὸς αὐτός ἐστι « ζωὴ εἰλικρινῶς μία »; οὐχὶ καὶ ἐπ' αὐτοῦ « ἕνα καὶ τὸν αὐτὸν εἶναι » προσήκει « λόγον, κἂν τοῖς ὀνόμασιν ἢ τῷ τρόπῳ καὶ τῇ τάξει φαίνηται διάφορος »; οὐχὶ καὶ ἐπ' ἐκείνου « τῶν δύο » τὸ « ἕτερον ἐξ ἀνάγκης » στήσεται, « ἢ καὶ τὸ πρᾶγμα τὸ δηλούμενον πάντως ἕτερον ἢ μηδὲ τὸν δηλοῦντα λόγον, μηδενὸς ὑποκειμένου πράγματος παρὰ τὴν ζωὴν αὐτοῦ, ᾧ τις ἂν ἢ τὴν διάνοιαν ἐπερείσειεν ἢ τὸν ἕτερον λόγον ἐπιρρίψειεν »; οὐδὲν παρ' ἡμῶν τοῖς περὶ τοῦ πατρὸς εἰρημένοις παρὰ τοῦ Εὐνομίου ἐμμέμικται, ἀλλ' ἐπ' αὐτῆς ἤλθομεν τῆς ὁμολογίας καὶ τῆς ἀκολουθίας, μόνον „τοῦ υἱοῦ” παρενθέντες τὸ ὄνομα. εἰ οὖν καὶ αὐτὸς μία ζωὴ εἰλικρινὴς πάσης συνθέσεως καὶ διπλόης κεχωρισμένη καὶ οὐδὲν ὑπόκειται πρᾶγμα παρὰ τὴν τοῦ υἱοῦ ζωήν (πῶς γὰρ « ἂν » ἐν τῷ ἁπλῷ μίξις ἀλλοτρίου πράγματος ὑποπτεύοιτο; οὐ γὰρ ἂν ἔτι ἁπλοῦν εἴη τὸ μεθ' ἑτέρου νοούμενον), ἁπλῆ δὲ ζωὴ καὶ ἡ τοῦ πατρὸς οὐσία, ἁπλῆς δὲ ζωῆς κατ' αὐτὸν τόν τε τῆς ζωῆς καὶ τὸν τῆς ἁπλότητος λόγον οὐδεμία τίς ἐστι διαφορά, οὔτε ἐπιτάσεως οὔτε ὑφέσεως οὔτε τῆς κατὰ τὸ ποσὸν ἢ ποιὸν ἑτερότητος τὴν παραλλαγὴν ἐμποιούσης, ἀνάγκη πᾶσα τὰ ταῖς αὐταῖς ἐννοίαις συμβαίνοντα καὶ ὑπὸ τῶν αὐτῶν προσηγοριῶν ὀνομάζεσθαι. εἰ οὖν ἓν τὸ πρᾶγμα τὸ κατὰ τὴν ἁπλότητα τῆς ζωῆς ἐν πατρὶ καὶ υἱῷ καταλαμβάνεται, οὐδεμίαν τοῦ τῆς ἁπλότητος λόγου καθὼς εἴρηται παραλλαγὴν δεχομένου, ἀνάγκη πᾶσα τὸ τῷ ἑνὶ ἐφαρμοζόμενον ὄνομα καὶ πρὸς τὸ ἕτερον προσφυῶς ἔχειν: ὥστε εἰ ἡ ἁπλότης τῆς τοῦ πατρὸς ζωῆς τῷ τῆς ἀγεννησίας ὀνόματι διασημαίνεται, μηδὲ πρὸς τὴν τοῦ υἱοῦ ἁπλότητα τὴν φωνὴν ἀνοικείως ἔχειν. ὥσπερ γὰρ τὸ λογικὸν καὶ θνητὸν καὶ νοῦ καὶ ἐπιστήμης δεκτικὸν ἄνθρωπος ὀνομάζεται ὁμοίως ἐπί τε τοῦ Ἀδὰμ καὶ τοῦ Ἄβελ καὶ οὐδὲν τὴν τῆς φύσεως ἐπωνυμίαν ὑπήμειψεν, οὔτε ἐπὶ τοῦ Ἄβελ τὸ διὰ γεννήσεως οὔτε ἐπὶ τοῦ Ἀδὰμ τὸ ἄνευ γεννήσεως εἰς ζωὴν παρελθεῖν, οὕτως εἴπερ τὸ ἁπλοῦν καὶ ἀσύνθετον τῆς τοῦ πατρὸς ζωῆς ὄνομα τὴν ἀγεννησίαν ἔχει, ὡσαύτως καὶ ἐπὶ τῆς τοῦ υἱοῦ ζωῆς ἡ αὐτὴ ἔννοια τῇ αὐτῇ φωνῇ κατ' ἀνάγκην ἐφαρμοσθήσεται, εἴπερ « δεῖ », καθώς φησιν ὁ Εὐνόμιος, « δυοῖν θάτερον, ἢ καὶ τὸ πρᾶγμα τὸ δηλούμενον πάντως ἕτερον ἢ μηδὲ τὸν δηλοῦντα λόγον ἕτερον » εἶναι.