Diocese of Ibagué

 St. Ibar

 Diocese of Ibarra

 Ibas

 Pierre Le Moyne, Sieur d'Iberville

 Ibora

 Iceland

 Iconium

 Iconoclasm

 Christian Iconography

 Iconostasis

 Idaho

 Idea

 Idealism

 Idiota

 Idolatry

 Idumea

 Diocese of Iglesias

 José Iglesias de la Casa

 Bl. Ignacio de Azevedo

 St. Ignatius Loyola

 St. Ignatius of Antioch

 St. Ignatius of Constantinople

 Ignorance

 IHS

 St. Ildephonsus

 Illegitimacy

 Illinois

 Illinois Indians

 St. Illtyd

 Illuminati

 Illyria

 Veneration of Images

 Imagination

 Carlo Giuseppe Imbonati

 Maximus von Imhof

 Imitation of Christ

 Immaculate Conception

 Congregation of the Immaculate Conception

 Immanence

 Immortality

 Immunity

 Diocese of Imola

 Innocenzo di Pietro Francucci da Imola

 Impanation

 Canonical Impediments

 Imposition of Hands

 Impostors

 Improperia

 Incardination and Excardination

 Sisters of Charity of the Incarnate Word

 Order of the Incarnate Word and Blessed Sacrament

 The Incarnation

 Incense

 Incest

 Elizabeth Inchbald

 In Cœna Domini

 In Commendam

 Civil Incorporation of Church Property

 Index of Prohibited Books

 India

 Indiana

 Diocese of Indianapolis

 Bureau of Catholic Indian Missions

 American Indians

 Patriarchate of the East Indies

 Religious Indifferentism

 Individualism

 Individual, Individuality

 Indo-China

 Induction

 Indulgences

 Apostolic Indulgences

 Pontifical Indult

 St. Ine

 Infallibility

 Volume 9

 Infamy

 Infanticide

 Stefano Infessura

 Infidels

 Infinity

 Infralapsarians

 Giovanni Inghirami

 Ven. Francis Ingleby

 University of Ingolstadt

 Ven. John Ingram

 Jean-Auguste Dominique Ingres

 Ingulf

 Richard of Ingworth

 Injustice

 Pope Innocent I

 Pope Innocent II

 Pope Innocent III

 Pope Innocent IV

 Pope Bl. Innocent V

 Pope Innocent VI

 Pope Innocent VII

 Pope Innocent VIII

 Pope Innocent IX

 Pope Innocent X

 Pope Innocent XI

 Pope Innocent XII

 Pope Innocent XIII

 Sts. Innocentius

 Innsbruck University

 In Partibus Infidelium

 In Petto

 Inquisition

 Canonical Inquisition

 Asylums and Care for the Insane

 Insanity

 Early Christian Inscriptions

 Inspiration of the Bible

 Installation

 Instinct

 Institute of Mary

 Institute of Mission Helpers of the Sacred Heart

 Irish Institute of the Blessed Virgin Mary

 Institute of the Brothers of the Christian Schools

 Roman Historical Institutes

 Canonical Institution

 Intellect

 Vicariate Apostolic of Intendencia Oriental y Llanos de San Martín

 Intention

 Intercession (Mediation)

 Episcopal Intercession

 Interdict

 Psychology of Interest

 Interest

 Interims

 Internuncio

 Biblical Introduction

 Introit

 Intrusion

 Intuition

 Inventory of Church Property

 Canonical Investiture

 Conflict of Investitures

 Invitatorium

 School of Iona

 Ionian Islands

 Ionian School of Philosophy

 Ionopolis

 Iowa

 Arnold Ipolyi

 Bl. Ippolito Galantini

 Ipsus

 Ireland

 Irish Literature

 Ven. William Ireland

 St. Irenaeus

 Sister Irene

 Irenopolis

 Ignacio de Iriarte

 Irish, in Countries other than Ireland

 Irish College, in Rome

 Irish Colleges, on the Continent

 Irish Confessors and Martyrs

 Irnerius

 Iroquois

 Irregularity

 Irremovability

 Irvingites

 Isaac

 Isaac of Armenia

 Isaac of Nineveh

 Isaac of Seleucia

 Isabella I

 Bl. Isabel of France

 Isaias

 Isaura

 Diocese of Ischia

 Diocese of Isernia and Venafro

 St. Isidore of Pelusium

 St. Isidore of Seville

 Isidore of Thessalonica

 St. Isidore the Labourer

 Isionda

 José Francisco de Isla

 Islam

 Isleta Pueblo

 Simon Islip

 Ismael

 Ispahan

 Israelites

 Issachar

 Issus

 St. Ita

 Italians in the United States

 Italo-Greeks

 Italy

 Italian Literature

 Ite Missa Est

 Itineraria

 Itinerarium

 Franz Ittenbach

 St. Ives

 Levi Silliman Ives

 St. Ivo of Chartres

 Ivory

 Diocese of Ivrea

 Fernando de Alba Ixtlilxochitl

Intuition


Intuition (Latin intueri, to look into) is a psychological and philosophical term which designates the process of immediate apprehension or perception of an actual fact, being, or relation between two terms and its results. Hence the words Intuitionism or Intuitionalism mean those systems in philosophy which consider intuition as the fundamental process of our knowledge or at least give to intuition a large place (the Scottish school), and the words Intuitive Morality and Intuitional Ethics denote those ethical theories which base morality on an intuitive apprehension of the moral principles and laws, or consider intuition as capable of distinguishing the moral qualities of our actions (Shaftesbury, Hutcheson, Reid, Dugald Stewart). As an element of educational method intuition means the grasp of knowledge by concrete, experimental or intellectual, ways of apprehension. The immediate perception of sensuous or material objects by our senses is called sensuous or empirical intuition, the immediate apprehension of intellectual or immaterial objects by our intelligence is called intellectual intuition. It may be remarked that Kant calls empirical intuitions our knowledge of objects through sensation, and pure intuition our perception of space and time as the forms a priori of sensibility. Again, our intuitions may be called external or internal, according as the objects perceived are external objects or internal objects or acts.

The importance of intuition as a process and element of knowledge is easily seen if we observe that it is intuition which furnishes us with the first experimental data as well as with the primary concepts and the fundamental judgments or principles which are the primitive elements and the foundation of every scientific and philosophical speculation. This importance, however, has been falsely exaggerated by some modern philosophers to an extent which tends to destroy both supernatural religion and the validity of human reason. There has been an attempt, on their part, to make of intuition, under different names, the central and fundamental element of our power of acquiring knowledge, and the only process or operation that can put us into contact with reality. So we have the creation or intuition of the ego and non ego in the philosophy of Fichte; the intuition or intellectual vision of God claimed by the Ontologists in natural theology (see ONTOLOGISM), W. James's unconscious intuition or religious experience (The Varieties of Religious Experience), Bergson's philosophy of pure intuition the experience or experiential consciousness of the Divine of the Modernists (Encyclical "Pascendi gregis"). According to the Ontologists, our knowledge of notions endowed with the character of necessity and universality, as well as our idea of the Infinite, are possible only through an antecedent intuition of God present in us. Other philosophers start from the principle that human reasoning is unable to give us the knowledge of things in themselves. The data of common sense, our intellectual concepts, and the conclusions reached through the process of discursive reasoning do not, they say primarily represent reality, but acting under diverse influences such as those of our usual and practical needs, common sense and discursive reason result in a deformation of reality; the value of their data and conclusions is one of practical usefulness rather than one of true representation (see PRAGMATISM). Intuition alone, they maintain, is able to put us in communication with reality and give us a true knowledge of things. Especially in regard to religious truths, some insist, it is only through intuition and internal experience that we can acquire them. "God", says the Protestant A. Sabatier in his Esquisse d'une philosophie de la religion, "is not a phenomenon which can be observed outside of the ego, a truth to be demonstrated by logical reasoning. He who does not feel Him in his heart, will never find Him outside . . . . We never become aware of our piety without at the same time feeling a religious emotion and perceiving in this very emotion, more or less obscurely, the object and the cause of religion, namely, God." The arguments used by the Schoolmen to prove the existence of God, say the Modernists, have now lost all their value; it is by the religious feeling, by an intuition of the heart that we apprehend God (Encycl. "Pascendi gregis" and "II programma dei modernisti").

Such theories have their source in the principle of absolute subjectivism and relativism — the most fundamental error in philosophy. Starting with Kant's proposition that we cannot know things as they are in themselves but only as they appear to us, that is, under the subjective conditions that our human nature necessarily imposes on them, they arrive at the conclusion that our rational knowledge is subjectively relative, and that its concepts, principles, and process of reasoning are therefore essentially unable to reach external and transcendental realities. Hence their recourse to intuition and immanence. But it is easy to show that if intuition is necessary in every act of knowledge, it remains essentially insufficient in our present life, for scientific and philosophical reflection. In our knowledge of nature we start from observation; but observation remains fruitless if it is not verified by a series of inductions and deductions. In our knowledge of God, we may indeed start from our nature and from our insufficiency and aspirations, but if we want to know Him we have to demonstrate, by discursive reasoning, His existence as an external and transcendent Cause and Supreme End. We may indeed, in Ethics have an intuition of the notion of duty, of the need of a sanction; but these intuitive notions have no moral value if they are not connected with the existence of a Supreme Ruler and Judge, and this connection can be known only through reasoning. The true nature, place, and value of intuition in human knowledge are admirably put forth in the Scholastic theory of knowledge. For the Schoolmen the intuitive act of intellectual knowledge is, by its nature, the most perfect act of knowledge, since it is an immediate apprehension of and contact with reality in its concrete existence, and our supreme reward m the supernatural order will consist in the intuitive apprehension of God by our intelligence: the beatific vision. But in our present conditions of earthly life, our knowledge must of necessity make use of concepts and reasoning. All our knowledge has its starting-point in the intuitive data of sense experience, but in order to penetrate the nature of these data, their laws and causes, we must have recourse to abstraction and discursive reasoning. It is also through those processes and through them alone that we can arrive at the notion of immaterial beings and of God himself (St. Thomas "Contra Gentes", I, 12; "Summa Theologica" I:84-88, etc.) . Our mind has the intuition of primary principles (intellectus) but their application, in order to give us a scientific and philosophical knowledge of things, is subject to the laws of abstraction and successive reasoning (ratio, discursus, cf. I:58:3, II-II:49:5, ad 2um). Such a necessity is, as it were, a normal defect of human intelligence; it is the natural limit which determines the place of the human mind in the scale of intellectual beings.

Concepts and reasoning therefore are in themselves inferior to intuition; but they are the normal processes of human knowledge. They are not, however a deformation of reality, though they give only an imperfect and inadequate representation of reality — and the more so according to the excellency of the objects represented — they are a true representation of it.

GEORGE M. SAUVAGE