Aachen , in French, Aix-la-Chapelle, the name by which the city is generally known in Latin Aquæ Grani, later Aquisgranum, is the capital of a presid

 Aaron

 Abaddon

 Abandonment

 Pedro Abarca

 Abarim

 Abba

 Antoine d'Abbadie

 Abban

 Abbé

 Jean Baptiste Abbeloos

 Abbess

 Abbey

 Abbo Cernuus

 St. Abbon

 Abbot

 Henry Abbot

 Methods of Abbreviation

 Ecclesiastical Abbreviations

 Abbreviators

 Abdera

 Abdias

 Abdias of Babylon

 Abdication

 Sts. Abdon and Sennen

 Abduction

 Abecedaria

 Abecedarians

 Abel (1)

 Abel (2)

 Peter Abelard

 Louis Abelly

 Abenakis

 Abraham-ben-Méir Aben-Ezra

 Inscription of Abercius

 John Abercromby

 Robert Abercromby

 Diocese of Aberdeen

 University of Aberdeen

 Moritz von Aberle

 Legend of Abgar

 Abiathar

 Abila

 Abbey of Abingdon

 Thomas Abington

 Missions among the Abipones

 Abisai

 Abjuration

 Abo

 Abner

 Abomination of Desolation

 Abortion

 Physical Effects of Abortion

 Charles François d'Abra de Raconis

 Don Isaac Abrabanel

 Abraham

 Abraham (in Liturgy)

 Bosom of Abraham

 Abraham a Sancta Clara

 Abraham Ecchelensis

 Abrahamites

 Nicholas Abram

 Abrasax

 Absalom

 Absalon of Lund

 Absinthe

 Absolute

 Absolution

 Abstemii

 Abstinence

 Physical Effects of Abstinence

 Abstraction

 Abthain

 Theodore Abucara

 Abundius

 Abydus

 Abyss

 Abyssinia

 Acacia

 Acacians

 Acacius, Bishop of Beroea

 Acacius, Bishop of Caesarea

 Acacius, Patriarch of Constantinople

 St. Acacius

 Roman Academies

 French Academy

 Acadia

 Acanthus (see)

 Acanthus (plant)

 Acathistus

 St. Acca

 Accaron

 Accentus Ecclesiasticus

 Acceptance

 Acceptants

 Accession

 Diocese of Arras

 Councils of Arras

 Pablo José Arriaga

 Juan Arricivita

 Nicola Arrighetti

 Nicolò Arrighetti

 Arsacidæ

 Arsenius Autorianos

 St. Arsenius

 Arsinoe

 Accessus

 Artemon

 James Arthur

 Thomas Arthur

 Articles of Faith

 Organic Articles

 Artoklasia

 Bachelor of Arts

 Faculty of Arts

 Master of Arts

 Seven Liberal Arts

 Acciajuoli

 Artvin

 Thomas Arundel

 Thomas Arundell

 St. Asaph

 Ascalon

 Ascelin

 Ascendente Domino

 Ascension

 Feast of the Ascension

 Asceticism

 Accident

 Joseph, Ritter von Aschbach

 Diocese of Ascoli-Piceno

 Diocese of Ascoli, Satriano, and Cirignola

 Aseity

 Aseneth

 Aser

 Asgaard

 Ash Wednesday

 George Ashby

 Thomas Ashby

 Acclamation

 Ashes

 Ven. Ralph Ashley

 John Ashton

 Ven. Roger Ashton

 Asia

 Asia Minor

 Asiongaber

 Robert Aske

 Asmodeus

 Aspendus

 Acclamation (in Papal Elections)

 Asperges

 Martin Aspilcueta

 The Ass (in Caricature of Christian Beliefs and Practices)

 Prefecture Apostolic of Assam

 Assemani

 Assemblies of the French Clergy

 John Asser

 Feast of Asses

 Assessor of the Holy Office

 Assessors

 Biblical Accommodation

 St. Assicus

 Assideans

 Physiological Assimilation

 Psychological Assimilation

 Diocese of Assisi

 Assistant at the Pontifical Throne

 Assize of Clarendon

 Volume 1

 Volume 3

 Assizes of Jerusalem

 Accomplice

 Ignaz Assmayer

 Right of Voluntary Association

 Association of Ideas

 Association of Priestly Perseverance

 Pious Associations

 Assuerus

 Little Sisters of the Assumption

 Sisters of the Assumption

 Feast of the Assumption of the Blessed Virgin Mary

 Assur (1)

 Francesco Accursius

 Assur (2)

 Assyria

 Asterisk

 Asterius

 Diocese of Asti

 Aston

 Diocese of Astorga

 Astrology

 Astronomy

 Astronomy in the Bible

 Paul-Thérèse-David d'Astros

 Acephali

 Jean Astruc

 Atahuallpa

 Juan Santos Atahualpa

 Atavism

 Vicariate Apostolic of Athabasca

 Athanasian Creed

 St. Athanasius

 Atheism

 Abbey of Athelney

 Athenagoras

 Archdiocese of Acerenza

 Athenry

 Christian Athens

 Modern Diocese of Athens

 Joseph Athias

 Mount Athos

 Juan de Atienza

 James Atkinson

 Nicholas Atkinson

 Paul Atkinson of St. Francis

 Sarah Atkinson

 Achab

 Ven. Thomas Atkinson

 Atom

 Atomism

 Day of Atonement

 Doctrine of the Atonement

 Atrib

 Atrium

 Attainder

 St. Attala

 Attalia

 Achaia

 Michael Attaliates

 Atticus

 Councils of Attigny

 Attila

 Jean Denis Attiret

 Atto

 Atto of Pistoia

 Atto of Vercelli

 St. Attracta

 Divine Attributes

 Achaicus

 Attrition

 Attuda

 Jean-Michel-d'Astorg Aubarède

 Jean-Antoine d'Aubermont

 Joseph Aubery

 François Hédelin, Abbé d'Aubignac

 Pierre d'Aubusson

 Archdiocese of Auch

 Diocese of Auckland

 Auctorem Fidei

 Achaz

 Pontifical Audiences

 Giovanni Battista Audiffredi

 J. M. Vincent Audin

 Guglielmo Audisio

 Auditor

 Audran

 Leopold Auenbrugger

 Jobst Bernhard von Aufsees

 Edmond Auger

 Augilæ

 Lucas d'Achéry

 Diocese of Augsburg

 Synods of Augsburg

 Augusta

 Augustin von Alfeld

 Rule of Saint Augustine

 St. Augustine of Canterbury

 St. Augustine of Hippo

 Teaching of St. Augustine of Hippo

 Works of St. Augustine of Hippo

 Augustinians of the Assumption

 Antonius Augustinus

 Augustinus-Verein

 Achiacharus

 Augustopolis

 Augustus

 Aumbry

 St. Aunarius

 Aurea

 Aurelian

 Aureliopolis

 Aurelius

 Marcus Aurelius Antoninus

 Petrus Aureoli

 Achimaas

 Auriesville

 Giovanni Aurispa

 Aurora Lucis Rutilat

 Ausculta Fili

 Decimus Magnus Ausonius

 John Austin

 Australia

 St. Austrebertha

 St. Austremonius

 Austro-Hungarian Monarchy

 Achimelech

 Authentic

 Authenticity of the Bible

 Civil Authority

 Authorized Version

 Autocephali

 Autos Sacramentales

 Ambrose Autpert

 Joseph Autran

 Diocese of Autun

 Auxentius

 Achitopel

 Councils of Auxerre

 Auxiliary Bishop

 Auxilius of Naples

 Ava

 Nicola Avancini

 Avarice

 Avatār

 Pierre du Bois, Baron d'Avaugour

 Ave Maris Stella

 Ave Regina

 Diocese of Achonry

 Diocese of Avellino

 Avempace

 Fernando Avendano

 Averroes

 Diocese of Aversa

 Avesta

 Theological Aspects of Avesta

 Avicebron

 Avicenna

 Avignon

 Achor Valley

 University of Avignon

 Diocese of Avila

 Francisco de Avila

 Sancho de Avila

 St. Avitus

 Order of Aviz

 Council of Avranches

 Philippe Avril

 Axum

 Diocese of Ayacucho

 Achrida

 Fray Francisco de Ayeta

 Lucas Vásquez de Ayllón

 James Ambrose Dominic Aylward

 Aymará

 Aymeric of Piacenza

 Féliz de Azara

 Aristaces Azaria

 Brother Azarias

 Luiz de Azevedo

 Juan Azor

 Johann Heinrich Achterfeldt

 Azores

 Azotus

 Aztecs

 Azymes

 Azymites

 Theodore William Achtermann

 Valens Acidalius

 Diocese of Aci-Reale

 Leopold Ackermann

 Acmonia

 Acoemetae

 Acolouthia

 Acolyte

 Joaquín Acosta

 José de Acosta

 Diocese of Acquapendente

 Acquaviva

 Claudius Acquaviva

 Diocese of Acqui

 Acre

 Acrostic

 Acta Pilati

 Acta Sanctæ Sedis

 Acta Sanctorum Hiberniæ

 Acta Triadis Thaumaturgæ

 Act of Settlement (Irish)

 Charles Januarius Acton

 John Acton

 John Emerich Edward Dalberg Acton, Baron Acton

 John Francis Edward Acton

 Canonical Acts

 Human Acts

 Indifferent Acts

 Acts of the Apostles

 Acts of Roman Congregations

 Actus et Potentia

 Actus primus

 Actus Purus

 Acuas

 St. Adalard

 Adalbert

 Adalbert I

 St. Adalbert (of Bohemia)

 St. Adalbert (of Germany)

 Ad Apostolicae Dignitatis Apicem

 Ad Limina Apostolorum

 Ad Sanctam Beati Petri Sedem

 Ad Universalis Ecclesiae

 Adam

 Adam in Early Christian Liturgy and Literature

 Books of Adam

 Adam of Bremen

 Adam of Fulda

 Adam of Murimuth

 Adam of Perseigne

 Adam of St. Victor

 Adam of Usk

 John Adam

 Nicholas Adam

 Adam Scotus

 Andrea Adami da Bolsena

 Adamites

 St. Adamnan

 James Adams

 Ven. John Adams

 Diocese of Adana

 Adar

 Ferdinando d'Adda

 Addas

 Liturgy of Addeus and Maris

 Ecclesiastical Addresses

 Archdiocese of Adelaide

 St. Adelaide, Abbess

 St. Adelaide (Adelheid)

 John Placid Adelham

 Adelmann

 Adelophagi

 Vicariate Apostolic of Aden

 Adeodatus

 Pope St. Adeodatus

 Adeste Fideles

 Adjuration

 Administrator

 Administrator (of Ecclesiastical Property)

 Canonical Admonitions

 Admont

 St. Ado of Vienne

 Adonai

 Adonias

 Adoption

 Canonical Adoption

 Supernatural Adoption

 Adoptionism

 Adoration

 Perpetual Adoration

 Francis Adorno

 Adoro Te Devote

 Diocese of Adria

 Pope Adrian I

 Pope Adrian II

 Pope St. Adrian III

 Pope Adrian IV

 Pope Adrian V

 Pope Adrian VI

 St. Adrian of Canterbury

 Adrian of Castello

 Adrianople

 Christian Kruik van Adrichem

 Adso

 Diego Francisco Aduarte

 Adullam

 Adulteration of Food

 Adultery

 Advent

 Adventists

 Book of Advertisements

 Advocates of Roman Congregations

 Advocates of St. Peter

 Advocatus Diaboli

 Advocatus Ecclesiæ

 Advowson

 Adytum

 St. Aedan of Ferns

 Aedh of Kildare

 Bl. Aegidius of Assisi

 Ægidius of Viterbo

 Aelfric, Abbot of Eynsham

 Ælnoth

 St. Ælred

 Æneas of Gaza

 St. Aengus (the Culdee)

 Ænon

 Æons

 Aër

 Aërius of Pontus

 Æsthetics

 Æterni Patris (Pius IX)

 Æterni Patris (Leo XIII)

 Aëtius

 Affinity (in the Bible)

 Affinity (in Canon Law)

 Affirmation

 Afflighem

 Denis Auguste Affre

 St. Afra

 Africa

 Early African Church

 African Liturgy

 African Synods

 Agabus

 Agape

 Agapetae

 Agapetus

 Pope St. Agapetus I

 Pope Agapetus II

 William Seth Agar

 St. Agatha

 Agathangelus

 Agathias

 Pope St. Agatho

 Agaunum

 Agostini Agazzari

 Council of Agde

 Canonical Age

 Age of Reason

 Diocese of Agen

 Agents of Roman Congregations

 Aggeus (Haggai)

 Unjust Aggressor

 Raymond d'Agiles

 St. Agilulfus

 Agios O Theos

 Giuseppe Agnelli

 Fra Guglielmo Agnelli

 Bl. Agnellus of Pisa

 Andreas Agnellus of Ravenna

 St. Agnes of Assisi

 Bl. Agnes of Bohemia

 St. Agnes of Montepulciano

 St. Agnes of Rome

 Maria Gaetana Agnesi

 Agnetz

 Agnoetae

 Agnosticism

 Agnus Dei

 Agnus Dei (in Liturgy)

 Agonistici

 Agony of Christ

 Paolo Agostini

 Bl. Agostino Novello

 Charles Constance César Joseph Matthieu d'Agoult

 Archdiocese of Agra

 Agram

 Agrapha

 Agrarianism

 Maria de Agreda

 Agria

 St. Agricius

 Alexander Agricola

 George Agricola

 Rudolph Agricola

 Heinrich Cornelius Agrippa of Nettesheim

 Agrippinus

 Diocese of Aguas Calientes

 Joseph Saenz de Aguirre

 Ahicam

 Ahriman and Ormuzd

 Johann Caspar Aiblinger

 Gregor Aichinger

 St. Aidan of Lindisfarne

 Duchess of Aiguillon

 Mary Aikenhead

 St. Ailbe

 St. Aileran

 Family of d'Ailleboust

 Pierre d'Ailly

 Mateo Aimerich

 Diocese of Aire

 Giacomo Maria Airoli

 Aisle

 Aistulph

 Archdiocese of Aix

 Councils of Aix-en-Provence

 Diocese of Ajaccio

 Akhmin

 Michael and Nicetas Akominatos

 Alabama

 Alabanda

 Alabaster

 Diocese of Alagoas

 Pietro Alagona

 Alain de l'Isle

 Alalis

 Lucas Alaman

 Niccolò Alamanni

 Alan of Tewkesbury

 Alan of Walsingham

 Alanus de Rupe

 Alaska

 Diocese of Alatri

 Alb

 Diocese of Alba Pompeia

 St. Alban

 Albanenses

 Albania

 Albani

 Albano

 Diocese of Albany

 Diocese of Albenga

 Niccolo Albergati

 Alberic of Monte Cassino

 Alberic of Ostia

 Albero de Montreuil

 Giulio Alberoni

 Albert

 Albert II

 Bl. Albert

 St. Albert

 Bl. Albert Berdini of Sarteano

 Albert of Aachen

 Albert of Brandenburg

 Albert of Castile

 Albert of Stade

 Leandro Alberti

 Leone Battista Alberti

 Nicolò Albertini

 John Baptist Albertrandi

 Bl. Albertus Magnus

 Archdiocese of Albi

 Council of Albi

 Juan de Albi

 Sigismund Albicus

 Albigenses

 Albinus

 Johann G. Albrechtsberger

 Albright Brethren

 Afonzo de Albuquerque

 University of Alcalá

 Military Order of Alcántara

 Antonio de Alcedo

 Alchemy

 St. Alcmund

 Andrea Alciati

 Alcimus

 John Alcock

 Alcoholism

 Alcuin

 St. Aldegundis

 Aldersbach

 Aldfrith

 St. Aldhelm

 St. Aldric

 Ulissi Aldrovandi

 Leonard Alea

 Phillipe Alegambe

 Francisco Xavier Alegre

 Joseph Sadoc Alemany

 Giulio Alenio

 Archdiocese of Aleppo

 Diocese of Ales and Terralba

 Diocese of Alessandria della Paglia

 Galeazzo Alessi

 Diocese of Alessio

 Alexander

 Alexander (Early Bishops)

 Pope St. Alexander I

 Pope Alexander II

 Pope Alexander III

 Pope Alexander IV

 Pope Alexander V

 Pope Alexander VI

 Pope Alexander VII

 Pope Alexander VIII

 St. Alexander

 St. Alexander (II)

 St. Alexander (of Alexandria)

 Bl. Alexander Briant

 Alexander Natalis

 Alexander of Abonoteichos

 Alexander of Hales

 Alexander of Lycopolis

 Bl. Alexander Sauli

 Dom Jacques Alexandre

 Alexandria

 Councils of Alexandria

 Church of Alexandria

 Diocese of Alexandria

 Alexandrian Library

 Alexandrine Liturgy

 Alexian Nuns

 Alexians

 St. Alexis Falconieri

 St. Alexius

 Count Vittorio Alfieri

 Pietro Alfieri

 Alfonso de Zamora

 Alfonso of Burgos

 Michael Alford

 Alfred the Great

 St. Alfrida

 St. Alfwold

 Alger of Liége

 Diocese of Alghero

 Archdiocese of Algiers

 Algonquins

 Diocese of Alife

 Alimentation

 Alimony

 Aliturgical Days

 All Hallows College

 All Saints

 All Souls' Day

 Allah

 Diocese of Allahabad

 Paul Allard

 Leo Allatius

 Joseph Allegranza

 Antonio Allegri

 Gregorio Allegri

 Alleluia

 Jean Allemand

 Edward Patrick Allen

 Frances Allen

 George Allen

 John Allen (I)

 John Allen (II)

 William Allen

 August Allerstein

 Thomas William Allies

 Joseph Franz Allioli

 William Allison

 Allocution

 Allori

 William Allot

 Claude Allouez

 Alma

 Alma Redemptoris Mater

 Diego de Almagro

 John Almeida

 Diocese of Almeria

 Camillo Almici

 Ven. John Almond

 John Almond

 Oliver Almond

 Alms and Almsgiving

 St. Alnoth

 Alogi

 St. Aloysius Gonzaga

 A and Ω

 Alpha and Omega (in Jewish Theology)

 Christian Use of the Alphabet

 St. Alphonsus Liguori

 St. Alphonsus Rodriguez

 Prospero Alpini

 Alsace-Lorraine

 Diego Francisco Altamirano

 Altamura and Acquaviva

 Altar (in Liturgy)

 Altar (in the Greek Church)

 Altar (in Scripture)

 History of the Christian Altar

 Bl. Altmann

 St. Alto

 Diocese of Alton

 Diocese of Altoona

 Altruism

 Alumnus

 Niccolò Alunno

 Fernando Alvarez de Toledo, Duke of Alva

 Pedro d'Alva y Astorga

 Alonzo de Alvarado

 Fray Francisco de Alvarado

 Pedro de Alvarado

 Balthazar Alvarez

 Diego Alvarez

 Manoel Alvarez

 Alvarez de Paz

 St. Alypius

 José Antonio Alzate

 Johann Baptist Alzog

 Ama

 Giovanni Antonio Amadeo

 Dioceses of Amadia and Akra

 Amalarius of Metz

 St. Amalberga (1)

 St. Amalberga (2)

 Amalec

 Archdiocese of Amalfi

 Amalricians

 Amalricus Augerii

 St. Amandus

 Amasia

 Amastris

 Thaddeus Amat

 Amathus

 Diocese of Amazones

 Peter Ambarach

 Ambition

 Ambo

 Ambo (in the Russian and Greek Church)

 George d'Amboise

 Our Lady of Ambronay

 August Wilhelm Ambros

 St. Ambrose

 St. Ambrose of Camaldoli

 Bl. Ambrose of Sienna

 Ambrosian Basilica

 Ambrosian Chant

 Ambrosian Hymnography

 Ambrosian Library

 Ambrosian Liturgy and Rite

 Ambrosians

 Ambrosiaster

 Ambulatory

 Diocese of Amelia

 Denis Amelote

 Amen

 Amende Honorable

 Veit Amerbach

 America

 Pre-Columbian Discovery of America

 American College in Rome

 American College at Louvain

 South American College

 American Protective Association

 Francis Kerril Amherst

 Ven. John Amias

 Amice

 Antonio Amico

 Francesco Amico

 Diocese of Amida

 Diocese of Amiens

 Joseph Maria Amiot

 Amisus

 Daniel Ammen

 St. Ammon

 Ammon

 Ammonian Sections

 Ammonites

 Amorbach

 Amorios

 Amorrhites

 Eusebius Amort

 Amos

 Amovibility

 Vicariate Apostolic of Amoy

 André Marie Ampère

 Amphilochius of Iconium

 Amphilochius of Sida

 Amphoræ

 Abbey of Ampleforth

 Ampullæ

 Diocese of Ampurias

 Amra

 Amrah

 Amraphel

 Amsterdam

 Amulet

 Use and Abuse of Amulets

 Amyclae

 Jacques Amyot

 Anabaptists

 Pope St. Anacletus

 Anacletus II

 Anæsthesia

 Diocese of Anagni

 Analogy

 Analysis

 Anaphora

 Anarchy

 St. Anastasia

 Anastasiopolis

 St. Anastasius (1)

 Pope St. Anastasius I

 Pope Anastasius II

 Pope Anastasius III

 Pope Anastasius IV

 St. Anastasius (2)

 St. Anastasius Sinaita

 Anathema

 Anathoth

 St. Anatolia

 St. Anatolius (1)

 St. Anatolius (2)

 Anatomy

 Anazarbus

 Pedro de Añazco

 Joseph Anchieta

 Anchor

 Anchorites

 Ancient of Days

 Ancilla Dei

 Ciriaco d'Ancona

 Diocese of Ancona and Umana

 Ancren Riwle

 Ancyra

 Councils of Ancyra

 Andalusia

 William Henry Anderdon

 Anthony Maria Anderledy

 Henry James Anderson

 Lionel Albert Anderson

 Patrick Anderson

 James Anderton

 Ven. Robert Anderton

 Roger Anderton

 Thomas Anderton

 Heinrich Bernhard, Freiherr von Andlaw

 Ven. William Andleby

 Alonso Andrada

 Antonio de Andrada

 Diego Andrada de Payva

 Bernard André

 Yves Marie André

 Giovanni d'Andrea

 Bl. Andrea Dotti

 Andrea Pisano

 Andreas of Ratisbon

 Felix de Andreis

 Juan Andres

 St. Andrew (1)

 St. Andrew (2)

 St. Andrew Avellino

 Bl. Andrew Bobola

 St. Andrew Corsini

 Andrew of Caesarea

 St. Andrew of Crete

 Andrew of Lonjumeau

 Andrew of Rhodes

 St. Andrew the Scot

 William Eusebius Andrews

 Diocese of Andria

 Anemurium

 Felice Anerio

 Giovanni Francesco Anerio

 Filippo Anfossi

 Ange de Saint Joseph

 Ange de Sainte Rosalie

 Angel

 St. Angela Merici

 Bl. Angela of Foligno

 Francesco degli Angeli

 Girolamo degli Angeli

 Angelicals

 Fra Angelico

 Bl. Angelo Carletti di Chivasso

 Angelo Clareno da Cingoli

 Early Christian Representations of Angels

 Angels of the Churches

 Angelus

 Angelus Bell

 Angelus Silesius

 Anger

 Diocese of Angers

 University of Angers

 Notre Dame des Anges

 St. Angilbert

 Francesco Angiolini

 Priory of Anglesea

 Anglican Orders

 Anglicanism

 Timothy Warren Anglin

 Anglo-Saxon Church

 Anglona-Tursi

 Angola and Congo

 Diocese of Angora

 Diocese of Angoulême

 Diocese of Angra

 Pedro Angulo

 Vicariate Apostolic of Anhalt

 Pope St. Anicetus

 College and Church of the Anima (in Rome)

 Anima Christi

 Animals in Christian Art

 Animals in the Bible

 Animism

 Giovanni Animuccia

 Anise

 Anna

 Anna Comnena

 Ecclesiastical Annals

 Annas

 François Annat

 Annates

 St. Anne

 Sainte Anne d'Auray

 Sainte Anne de Beaupré

 Diocese of Annecy

 Joseph Annegarn

 Annibale d'Annibaldi

 Giuseppe d'Annibale

 Annius of Viterbo

 St. Anno

 Annunciation of the Blessed Virgin Mary

 Feast of the Annunciation of the Blessed Virgin Mary

 Orders of the Annunciation

 Louis-Pierre Anquetil

 Casto Innocenzio Ansaldi

 Giordano Ansaloni

 St. Anschar

 Councils of Anse

 Ansegisus

 St. Ansegisus

 St. Anselm (1)

 St. Anselm (2)

 Anselm of Laon

 Anselm of Liège

 St. Anselm of Lucca, the Younger

 Antoine Anselme

 Reyer Anslo

 Thomas Chisholm Anstey

 Antediluvians

 Pope St. Anterus

 Joseph Anthelmi

 Anthemius

 St. Anthony

 Orders of Saint Anthony

 St. Anthony of Padua

 Anthony of Sienna

 Anthony of the Mother of God

 Anthropomorphism

 Antichrist

 Antidicomarianites

 Antidoron

 Diocese of Antigonish

 Antimensium

 Antinoe

 Antinomianism

 Church of Antioch

 Antioch

 Antiochene Liturgy

 Antiochus of Palestine

 Antipater of Bostra

 Antipatris

 Antiphellos

 Antiphon

 Antiphon (in the Greek Church)

 Antiphon (in Greek Liturgy)

 Antiphonary

 Gregorian Antiphonary

 Antipodes

 Antipope

 Archdiocese of Antivari

 Vicariate Apostolic of Antofogaste

 Paul Gabriel Antoine

 Anton Ulrich

 Giacomo Antonelli

 Leonardo Antonelli

 Nicolò Maria Antonelli

 Giovanni Antoniano

 Silvio Antoniano

 Charles Antoniewicz

 St. Antoninus

 Antoninus Pius

 St. Antonio Maria Zaccaria

 Maria Antonio of Vicenza

 Antonius

 Franz Joseph Antony

 Antwerp

 Fray Domingo de la Anunciación

 Fray Juan de la Anunciación

 Diocese of Aosta

 Apaches

 Apameia

 Antonio Aparisi y Guijarro

 Apelles

 St. Aphian

 Aphraates

 Apiarius of Sicca

 Apocalypse

 Apocatastasis

 Apocrisiarius

 Apocrypha

 Apodosis

 Apollinarianism

 St. Apollinaris (1)

 St. Apollinaris (2)

 Apollinaris (the Elder)

 St. Apollinaris Claudius

 St. Apollonia

 Apollonius of Ephesus

 Apologetics

 Apolysis

 Apolytikion

 Apophthegmata Patrum

 Ferrante Aporti

 Apostasy

 Apostle (in Liturgy)

 Apostle Spoons

 Apostles

 Apostles' Creed

 Twelve Apostles of Erin

 Apostleship of Prayer

 Apostolic Camera

 Apostolic Churches

 Apostolic Church-Ordinance

 Apostolic Constitutions

 Apostolic Fathers

 Apostolic Letters

 Apostolic Majesty

 Apostolic See

 Apostolic Succession

 Apostolic Union of Secular Priests

 Apostolicae Curae

 Apostolicae Sedis Moderationi

 Apostolicæ Servitutis

 Apostolici

 Apostolici Ministerii

 Apostolici Regiminis

 Apostolicity

 Apostolicum Pascendi Munus

 Apotactics

 Apotheosis

 Apparitor

 Appeal as from an abuse

 Appeals

 Appetite

 Approbation

 Appropriation

 Apse

 Apse Chapel

 Apsidiole

 Council of Apt

 Aquarians

 Archdiocese of Aquila

 Aquila and Priscilla

 Aquileia

 Councils of Aquileia

 Diocese of Aquino, Sora, and Pontecorvo

 Arabia

 Vicariate Apostolic of Arabia

 Councils of Arabia

 Arabian School of Philosophy

 Arabici

 Arabissus

 Arad

 Monastic School of Aran

 Council of Aranda

 Philip Aranda

 Arason Jón

 Arator

 Prefecture Apostolic of Araucania

 Araucanians

 Antonio de Araujo

 Francisco de Araujo

 Arawaks

 Ignacio de Arbieto

 Arbitration

 St. Arbogast

 Abbey of Arbroath

 Missal of Arbuthnott

 Arca

 Our Lady of Arcachon

 Jacob Arcadelt

 Arcadiopolis

 Arcae

 Arcanum

 Arch

 Commission of Sacred Archæology

 Archange de Lyon

 Archbishop

 Archconfraternity

 Archdeacon

 Richard Archdeacon

 Archdiocese

 Archelais

 James Archer

 Court of Arches

 Archiereus

 Archimandrite

 Filippo Archinto

 Ecclesiastical Archives

 Archontics

 Archpriest

 Arcosolium

 Arculf

 Diocese of Ardagh

 Ardbraccan

 Priory of Ardchattan

 Edward Arden

 Notre Dame des Ardilliers

 Prince Charles d'Aremberg

 Areopagus

 Areopolis

 Diocese of Arequipa

 Arethas of Caesarea

 Arethusa

 Faustino Arévalo

 Rodríguez Sanchez de Arévalo

 Diocese of Arezzo

 Pierre de Voyer d'Argenson

 Argentine Republic

 Charles du Plessis d'Argentré

 Argos

 Luis Antonio Argüello

 Diocese of Argyll and the Isles

 John Argyropulos

 St. Arialdo

 Arianism

 Diocese of Ariano

 Francis Arias

 Pedro Arias de Avila

 Benedictus Arias Montanus

 Ariassus

 Aribo

 Arindela

 Ludovico Ariosto

 Aristeas

 Aristides

 Aristotle

 Arius

 Arizona

 Ark

 Arkansas

 Fray José Arlegui

 Synods of Arles

 Spanish Armada

 Archdiocese of Armagh

 Book of Armagh

 School of Armagh

 Georges d'Armagnac

 Mariano Armellino

 Armenia

 Armenierstadt

 Fray Nicolás Armentia

 Diocese of Armidale

 Arminianism

 Arnauld

 Thomas Augustine Arne

 Arni Thorlaksson

 Arnobius

 Arnold

 Arnold of Brescia

 Alberto Arnoldi

 Bartholomäus Arnoldi

 Arnolfo di Cambio

 Peter Joseph Arnoudt

 Veit Arnpeck

 Arnulf of Bavaria

 Arnulf of Lisieux

 St. Arnulf of Metz

Civil Authority


Civil Authority is the moral power of command, supported (when need be) by physical coercion, which the State exercises over its members. We shall consider here the nature, sources, limits, divisions, origin, and the true and false theories of authority. Authority is as great a necessity to mankind as sobriety, and as natural. By "natural" here is meant, not what accrues to man without any effort of his own (teeth, for example), but what man must secure, even with an effort, because without it he cannot well be man. It is natural to man to live in civil society; and where there is civil society, there must be authority. Anarchy is the disruption of society. Speaking generally, we may say no man loves isolation, solitude, loneliness, the life of a hermit; on the other hand, while many dislike the authority under which they live, no man wishes for anarchy. What malcontents aim at is a change of government, to get authority into their own hands and govern those who now govern them. Even the professed anarchist regards anarchy as a temporary expedient, a preparation for his own advent to power. Authority, then, in the abstract, every man loves and cherishes; and rightly so, for it is his nature to live in society, and society is kept together by authority. The model of hermits was St. Simeon Stylites, so called from his living on the top of a style, or pillar. That was his special vocation; he was no ordinary man. But the political philosopher considers man as man ordinarily and normally is. Two things would strike a stranger from Mars looking down upon this planet: how men on earth love herding together, and how they love moving about. Ordinary man can no more afford to be solitary than he can afford to be stationary, though Simeon Stylites was both. Solitary confinement is the severest of punishments, next to death. It is hard to say whether the solitude or the confinement, proves the more irksome. This simple point, that man cannot live alone, must be insisted upon, for all errors in the theory of authority are rooted in the assumption that man's living in society, and thereby coming to be governed by social authority, is something purely optional and conventional, a fashion which man could very well discard if he would, as he might discard the wearing of green clothes. Men who would make society a conventional arrangement, and authority a fashion of the hour, have appealed to the noble savage as the standard of humanity proper, forgetting that the savage is no solitary, but a member of a horde, to separate from which would be death, and to ignore the control of which would be death also. Man must live in society, and, in point of historical fact, men have always lived in society; every human development is a social progress. It is natural to man to live in society, to submit to authority, and to be governed by that custom of society which crystallizes into law.

And as it is natural to the individual, so is it natural also for the family to unite with others. Society cannot stop short at the family. As the individual is not sell-sufficient, neither is the family. The family grows and then multiplies. We have a society of families; and that society grown great, and controlled as it needs to be controlled by some common authority, passes into a self-sufficient, autonomous society, otherwise called a State. Hence civil authority is defined as the moral power of command, supported (when need be) by physical coercion, which the State exercises over its constituent members. Civil authority is of God, not by any revelation or positive institution, but by the mere fact that God is the Author of Nature, and Nature imperatively requires civil authority to be set up and obeyed. Nature cannot tolerate intemperance, nor anarchy either. And what Nature absolutely requires, or absolutely refuses as incompatible with her well-being, God commands, or God forbids. God then forbids anarchy; and in forbidding anarchy He enjoins submission to authority. In this sense, God is at the back of every State, binding men in conscience to observe the behests of the State within the sphere of its competence. "Let every soul be subject to higher powers: for there is no power but from God: and those that are, are ordained of God. . . . Wherefore be subject of necessity, not only for wrath, but also for conscience sake. . . . For they are the ministers of God, . . " (Horn. xiii, 1, 5, 6).

Obedience, being a practical thing and not a speculation, cannot abstract from the concrete facts of the case; it is paid to the powers that be, to the authority actually in possession. Obedience is as disobedience; men are never disobedient except to the government of the day. But there are limits to civil obedience, and to the competence of civil authority. As domestic obedience is not to be carried to the extent of rebellion against the civil government, so neither is the State to be obeyed as against God. It is not within the competence of the State to command anything and everything. The State cannot command what God could not command, for instance, idolatry. The authority of the State is absolute, that is to say, full and complete in its own sphere, and subordinate to no other authority within that sphere. But the authority of the State is not arbitrary; it is not available for the carrying out of every whim and caprice. Arbitrary government is irrational government; now no government is licensed to set reason aside. The government of God Himself is not arbitrary; as St. Thomas says: "God is not offended by us except at what we do against our own good" (Contra Gentiles, III, 122). The arbitrary use of authority is called tyranny. Such is the tyranny of an absolute monarch, of a council, of a class, or of a majority. The liberty of the subject is based on the doctrine that the State is not omnipotent. Legally omnipotent every State must be, but not morally. A legal enactment may be immoral, and then it cannot in conscience be obeyed; or it may be ultra vires, beyond the competence of the authority that enacts it, in which case compliance with the law is not a matter of obedience, but of prudence. In either case the law is tyrannical, and "a tyrannical law, not being according to reason, is not, absolutely speaking, a law, but rather a perversion of law" (St. Thomas, Summa Theol., la, 2ae, q. 92, art. 1, ad 4). Man is not all citizen. He is a member, a part of the State, and something else besides. "Man is not subservient to the civil community to the extent of his whole self, all that he is and all that he has" (St. Thomas, Summa Theol., 1a 2ae, q. 21, art. 4, ad 3). To say nothing of his eternal interests in his relations with his Maker, man has even in this life his domestic interests in the bosom of his family, his intellectual and artistic interests, none of which can be called political interests. Social and political life is not the whole of human life. Man is not the servant of the State in his every action. The State, the majority, or the despot, may demand of the individual more than he is bound to give. Were human society a conventional arrangement, were man, being perfectly well off in isolation from his fellows, to agree by way of freak to live in community with them, then we could assign no antecedent limits to civil authority. Civil authority would be simply what was bargained for and prescribed in the arbitrary compact which made civil society. As it is, civil authority is a natural means to a natural end and is checked by that end, in accordance with the Aristotelean principle that "the end in view sets limits to the means" (Aristotle, Politics, I, 9). The immediate end of civil authority is well set forth by Suarez (De legibus, LII, xi, 7) as "the natural happiness of the perfect, or self-sufficient, human community, and the happiness of individuals as they are members of such a community, that they may live therein peaceably and justly, with a sufficiency of goods for the preservation and comfort of their bodily life, and with so much moral rectitude as is necessary for this external peace and happiness". Happiness is an attribute of individuals. Individuals are not made happy by authority, but authority secures to them that tranquillity, that free hand for helping themselves, that restful enjoyment of their own just winnings, which is one of the conditions of happiness. Nor does authority make men virtuous, except according to that rough-hewn, outline virtue, which is called "social virtue", and consists mainly of justice. When the ancients spoke of "virtue" being the concern of the State, they meant justice and efficiency. Neither the virtue nor the happiness of individuals is cared for by the State except "as they are members of the civil community". In this respect, civil differs from domestic, or paternal, authority. The father cares for the members of his household one by one, singly and individually. The State cares for its members collectively, and for the individual only in his collective aspect. Hence it follows that the power of life and death is inherent in the State, not in the family. A man is hanged for the common good of the rest, never for his own good.

This, then, is one measure of authority, the end which the State has in view. Another is the stage of development at which any given particular State has arrived. For there is not one measure of authority common to all States. As the State develops, it grows in unity, and greater unity means an ampler measure of central authority. There is far more authority in the England of to-day than in the England of the Heptarchy. There was more authority in an Anglo-Saxon kingdom than in a horde of savages. In early civil societies there is no legislative authority, and no law, but only immemorial custom. There is little judicial authority, but injured men, or their families after their death, right their own wrongs, murder is restrained, not by judge, jury, and executioner, but by blood-feud. On the other hand, in highly civilized societies, especially those of a democratic character, the will of the people continually thrusts new functions upon government, such as education, the care of public health, the carrying of letters, the sending of telegrams. The recognition of this fact has been called "the principle of voluntary control". By it civil authority may be enlarged beyond its natural and essential limits. Like other principles, "the principle of voluntary control" may be pushed too far. Pushed to the limit, it would involve Socialism. Authority, though varying in amount, is as universal as man is everywhere. Man cannot live except under authority, as he cannot live out of civil society. It is by no convention, compact, or contract, that authority takes hold of him. It is a necessity of his nature. But while civil authority, or government, is natural and universal, the distribution of authority, otherwise called the form of government, or the constitution of the State, is a human convention, varying in various countries, and in the same country at different periods of its history. It is scarcely too much to say that there are as many various distributions of civil authority, or various forms of government, as there are varieties of vertebrate animals. They are classified as monarchies, aristocracies, democracies; but no two monarchies are quite alike, nor two democracies. Thus a democracy may be direct, as in ancient Athens, or representative, as in the United States. The monarchy of Edward VII is different from that of George III.

The one point fixed by nature, and by God, is that there must be authority everywhere, and that the authority existent for the time being, under such and such a form, be under that form obeyed; for since there is no actual authority in the country except under that form, to refuse to obey that is to refuse authority simply, and to revert to anarchy, which is against nature: just as a man having nothing but bread and cheese to eat, and refusing to eat his bread and cheese, under pretence that he much prefers mutton, condemns himself to starvation, which again is unnatural. But we must beware of saying of any particular form of authority, monarchy for example, or democracy either, what is true only of authority in the abstract, namely, that all nations are bound to live under it, and that never under any pretence can it be subverted. A country, once monarchical, is not eternally bound to monarchy; and circumstances are conceivable under which a republic might pass into monarchy, as Rome did under Augustus, much to its advantage. Authority rules by Divine right under whatsoever form it is established. No one form of government is more sacred and inviolate than another. Change of persons holding office is usually provided in the constitution, sometimes by rotation, sometimes by vote of the legislative assembly. No monarchical constitution provides for the change of the person of the monarch otherwise than by death or resignation. Change of the form of government can be effected constitutionally, but, as history shows, as often as not, it is brought about unconstitutionally. When the change is complete, the new government rules by right of accomplished fact. There must be authority in the country, and theirs is the only authority available.


DIVISIONS

The progress of civilization subdivides authority into legislative, judicial, and executive, and the latter again into civil and military. The king, or president, is chief of the executive. Authority again is subdivided into imperial and local, the latter emanating from the former and subordinate to it.


ORIGIN

The question of the origin of authority seems first to have been raised by the Roman lawyers. In their hands it assumed the concrete form of the origin of the imperial power. This power they argued to reside primarily in the Roman people; the people, however, did not exercise nor retain it, but transferred it by some implicit lex regia, or king-making ordinance, as a matter of course wholly, and irrevocably to each successive emperor at his accession. With the advent of Christianity, St. Paul's doctrine came into prominence, that authority is of God; yet in no clear way was it made out how it came of God until St. Thomas Aquinas showed that it was of God inasmuch as it was an essential of the human nature which God has created, according to the doctrine of Aristotle above exposed. Before St. Thomas arose, some churchmen had shown a disposition to cry down the civil power. They could not deny that it was of God, but they regarded it as one of the consequences of the sin of Adam, and argued that, but for the Fall, man would have lived free from coercive jurisdiction. They rehearsed the legend of Romulus, and the asylum that he opened for robbers. States, they said, usually have their origin in rapine and injustice. Others invested the pope with the plenitude of secular as well as spiritual authority, by the gift of Christ, and argued that kings reigned only as his vicegerents, even in civil matters. The Aristoteleanism of St. Thomas was opposed to all this. On the other hand, the imperial and royal party made a pope of the king or emperor; the civil ruler was as much an institution of Christ as the pope himself, and, like the pope, enjoyed a God-given authority, no portion of which could validly be taken from him. This is the doctrine of "the divine right of kings". According to it, in its rigour, in a State once monarchical, monarchy is forever the only lawful government, and all authority is vested in the monarch, to be communicated by him, to such as he may select for the time being to share his power. This "divine right of kings" (very different from the doctrine that all authority, whether of king or of republic, is from God), has never been sanctioned by the Catholic Church. At the Reformation it assumed a form exceedingly hostile to Catholicism, monarchs like Henry VIII, and James I, of England, claiming the fullness of spiritual as well as of civil authority, and this in such inalienable possession that no jot or tittle of prerogative could ever pass away from the Crown. Against these monstrous pretensions were fought the battles of Marston Moor and Naseby.

Against the same pretensions a more pacific warfare was waged by Francis Suarez, S.J.Suarez argued against James I that spiritual authority is not vested in the Crown, and that even civil authority is not the immediate gift of God to the king, but is given by God to the people collectively, and by them bestowed on the monarch, according to the theory of the Roman lawyers above mentioned, and according to Aristotle and St. Thomas. Authority, he asserted, is an attribute of a multitude assembled to form a State. By their nature they must form a State, and a State must have authority. Authority, therefore, is natural to mankind collectively; and whatever is natural, and rational, and indispensable for human progress, is an ordinance of God. Authority must be, and God will have it to be; but there is no such natural necessity of authority being all centred in one person. Authority is a Divine institution, but kings are a human invention. The saying is a platitude in our time; three centuries ago, when Suarez wrote, it was a bold and startling pronouncement. Suarez saved his loyalty by the concession that the people having bestowed the supreme power on His Majesty's ancestors ages ago, their posterity could not now resume it, but it must descend, like an heirloom, from the king to the king's son for all time. This concession was not everywhere borne in mind by posterity. Indeed it would appear a restriction on the development of a State for the distribution of authority to be thus fixed forever. In England at any rate the restriction has been broken through, and the king is not what he was in Stuart times, nor the Parliament either.


THEORIES

There have been two great outbreaks against excess of royal prerogative; one in England, in the middle of the seventeenth century; another in France, at the end of the eighteenth. Each of these two periods was marked by the appearance of a great political writer, Thomas Hobbes in England, Jean Jacques Rousseau in France. Hobbes was a philosopher, Rousseau a rhetorician. Whoever knows Hobbes well can have little to learn from Rousseau. Hobbes is rigidly logical; such inconsistencies as appear in him come from a certain timidity in speaking out, and a humility that approaches nigh to hypocrisy. Rousseau always speaks boldly, makes no pretence to orthodoxy, and frequently contradicts himself. His brilliant style won him the ear of Europe; he popularized Hobbes. To the philosopher, Rousseau is contemptible, but Hobbes is an antagonist worthy of any man's steel. The best that can be said of Rousseau in philosophy is that he drew out of Hobbes's principles conclusions which Hobbes was afraid to formulate. Hobbes made of the king a despot; Rousseau showed that, on Hobbesian principles, a king is no better than the people's bailiff, unless indeed, by military force or otherwise, he can prevent the people from assembling and decreeing his deposition.

Hobbes starts, and Rousseau after him, by contradicting Aristotle. According to Aristotle, man is "by nature a State-making animal"; the individual man, if he is to thrive at all, develops into the family man, and the family man into the citizen; and wherever there is a city, or a nation, there must be self-government, or, in other words, civil authority, whether vested in one or in many. Authority is the very breath of man's nostrils, as he is a progressive being. Isolation and anarchy are fatal to human progress. Effort, without which man cannot thrive, though it be an effort, and not an initial endowment passively received, Aristotle calls "natural". The State-making effort is "natural" to man; so is authority "natural", and, as such, of God, adds Thomas Aquinas. But Hobbes took "natural" in quite another sense. That he held to be "natural" which man is, antecedently to all effort and arrangement on his part to make himself better. Further, his philosophy was tinged with the Calvinism of his day, and he took it that man is of himself "desperately wicked". What was natural, then, was bad, bad on the whole. Reason being an original endowment of man, Hobbes allowed reason to be natural. He allowed also, with Plato, that wickedness is irrational, by which concession Hobbism is marked off from a celebrated theory stated at the beginning of the second book of Plato's Republic, to which theory in other respects it bears a strong resemblance; the theory being that right by nature is the interest of the stronger, and only by convention becomes the interest of the State.

This allowing of wickedness to be against reason is a weak point in the logic of Hobbes. But Hobbes would have it that reason is by nature utterly unable to contend with wickedness, that it is overborne by, and made subservient to, passion, and so is degraded into cunning, man becoming more wicked by his possession of reason. Of himself, in his "state of nature", Hobbesian man is a savage, solitary, sensual, and selfish. When two human beings meet, the natural impulse of each is to lord it over the other. By force, if he is strong, by stratagem, if he is weak, every man seeks to kill or enslave every other man that he meets. Man's life in this state of nature, says Hobbes, is "nasty, brutish, and short." So it would be, in an English fen, and in most other places. But Rousseau's imagination carried him to the Pacific Isles; he became enamoured of "the noble savage". He fell in with Hobbes's notion of the "natural", as being what man is and has antecedently to all human effort. But the "citizen of Geneva", as he called himself, was curiously free from Calvinistic bias, and believed enthusiastically in the primitive, unmade, natural goodness of man. In Hobbes's view, though not in Rousseau's, man had every reason for getting out of his "nasty" state of nature. This was done by a pact, or convention, of every man with all the rest of mankind, to give up solitude with its charms, its independence, and its liberty of preying upon neighbours, and to live in society, the social body thus formed having all the rights of the individuals contributing to form it. This compact of man with man to quit solitude and live in society, to abandon nature and submit to convention, was called by Rousseau, "The Social Contract". The body formed by it, commonly called the State, Hobbes termed "The Leviathan", upon the text of Job, xli, 24, "there is no power upon earth that can be compared with him. . . ."

To Hobbes and to Rousseau the State is omnipotent, containing in its one self absolutely all the rights of the citizens who compose it. The wielder of this tremendous power is the General Will, measured against which the will of the individual citizen is not only powerless, but absolutely non-existent. The individual gave up his will when he made the Social Contract. "No rights against the State", is a fundamental principle with Hobbes and Rousseau. To live in the State at all means compliance with every decree of the General Will. But there is a difficulty in locating this General Will. Hobbes, with laudable perspicacity, seeing that tyranny is better wielded by one man than by a multitude, contemplates the multitude resigning all their power into the hands of a Single Person, and denying themselves the right of meeting without his calling them together; so that, by the simple expedient of never calling them together, the Single Person may incapacitate the people from ever resuming the power which is only theirs when they are all assembled. The General Will in that case is the will of the Single Person. Hobbes's location of the General Will is not lacking in clearness. But Rousseau would have the sovereign authority to be the inalienable right of the multitude -- hence called the "Sovereign People". They may, if they will, employ a king, or even an emperor; but his majesty, in Rousseau's phrase, is "Prince" not "Sovereign", and at stated times, without his calling them together, the Sovereign People must meet and decide, first, whether they will continue to support a throne at all; secondly, whether the throne shall further be filled by the present occupant. Rousseau's location is also clear, so long as it is understood that the General Will is simply the will of the numerical majority of the Sovereign People. Such a General Will is ascertained by the simple process of counting heads. If in a State of 20,000 citizens, 15,000 vote aye, aye is the General Will, not the will of the majority only, but of the whole 20,000 together; for though 5,000 persons detest the proposal, such detestation lies only in the individual will, sometimes called the "casual will", and the individual will has ceased to exist by the Compact. Personally they detest the measure, but with their "Real Will" they approve it. Thus, as Rousseau says, they remain as free as the wild man in the woods, obey none but themselves, and follow their own will everywhere.

But a canker-worm lies at the root of this, as of all ultra-democratic doctrines. All originate in a manifestly false supposition, that one man is as good as another. In any sane polity, the predominant Intelligence must guide the counsels of the State, not the predominant Will, which may be no better than caprice. But intelligence is not necessarily attached to majorities. Rousseau himself falters in presence of this awkward truth, and re-states the General Will, as the will which the people have of good in general, albeit in a particular case they are mistaken in what they take to be good. Thus they will one thing, and vote for another. The Real Will in this case is not to be gathered from the actual vote of the majority. The Real Will is of that which the majority would have voted for, had they known better. Rousseau's theory contemplates "a people of gods", so he assures us. Such a people would scarce require any government. The ideal, sylvan creatures whom his imagination brings together to form the Social Contract, if not all very intelligent, may be supposed to be all good listeners to intelligent teaching, and thus Intelligence will govern the majority, and the vote of the majority will be an ideally Real Will. Government is an easy matter on such optimistic presuppositions. The eye, however, glances back upon Hobbes's ruffian primeval, "brutish and nasty". Hobbes's view of human nature must check that of Rousseau. Both views are extreme, and the truth lies between them. The democratic rule of a numerical majority is not of universal application. One has to consider the character of the people, and peoples vary. If in one age or place the people approximate to the character of "a people of gods", or angels, in another country or another time they may be more like devils. "Force, devoid of counsel, of its own bulk comes to a crash", says Horace (Odes, III, 4). That is the danger of the General Will.

Rousseau, with Hobbes to guide him, starts from a false supposition, that the natural state of man is savage solitude, not civil society; he proceeds through the false medium of the "Social Contract", false because society is not a thing of convention; false again, because out of all keeping with the evidence of history; and he is apt to end in the tyranny of a brute majority, trampling upon the rights and consciences of individuals; or again in anarchy, his disciples putting too literal a construction upon the promise that henceforth no man shall obey any other than himself.

The doctrines of Rousseau have not escaped the censure of the Church. Rousseau may be recognized in the following propositions, condemned in the Syllabus of Pius IX: "The State is the source and origin of all rights, and its rights are unlimited" (n. 39); "Authority is nothing else than numbers, and a sum of material forces" (n. 60): "It is allowable to refuse obedience to lawful princes, and even to rebel against them" (n. 63). Leo XIII, not content with condemning, teaches positive doctrine against Rousseau, to wit: the Aristotelean and Thomist doctrine already stated. Thus the Encyclical "Immortale Dei", of November, 1885:


In the theory of Hobbes and Rousseau, Authority is the outcome of contract, not between people and prince, but of every man with every other man to relinquish solitude and its rights, and live in civil society. Rousseau is instant in pronouncing that between people and prince there can be no contract, but the prince is a tenant at will, who may be turned out of doors, with or without reason, any day that the Sovereign People assemble to vote upon him. But there is another theory of contract, centuries older than Hobbes, a theory greatly cherished by Locke and the English Whigs, who found in it the justification of the expulsion of James II in 1688. In this theory, the contract is said to lie between the people and their ruler; the ruler is to be obeyed so long as he fulfils certain conditions, known as "the constitution". If he violates the constitution, he forfeits his authority and the people may cast him out. Thus ruler and subject are two "high contracting parties". The ruler has no superiority of status, but of contract only. On this it is to be observed, first, that such a contract lies not in the nature of things, and therefore is not to be taken for granted; but evidence in each particular case should be forthcoming of the contract having been made on those terms as a fact of history. Secondly, this asserted contract labours under the inconvenience that Job declared of old: " . . . in judgment. There is none that may be able to reprove both, and to put his hand between both" (Job, ix, 32, 33). The contract cannot be enforced at law, for lack of a judge; in case of dispute, each party pronounces in his own favour, and they are like to fight it out. The result is civil war, as between Charles I and his Parliament. But really ruler and subjects are not two "high contracting parties", as two nations are. The theory is prejudicial to the unity of the State, and countenances revolution. The theory was brought up to meet that delicate inquiry, "What is to be done when Government abuses its authority?" On which see "Moral Philosophy" (Stonyhurst Series), 338-343.

NEWMAN, Aristotle, Politics, (Clarendon Press, Oxford; there is a translation also by Weldon) I; ST. THOMAS, De Regimine Principum, I; LEO XIII, Encyclicals: Latin, five volumes (Tournai); English, The Pope and the People, Select Letters on Social Questions (New York); SUAREZ, Defensio Fidei, III, i, ii, iii; R. W. and A. T. CARLYLE, Medieval Political Theory in the West (London); GIERKE, Political Theories of the Middle Age, tr. by Maitland (Cambridge); RICKABY, Political and Moral Essays, The Origin and Extent of Civil Authority; HOBBES, Leviathan (Cambridge University Press); ROUSSEAU, Le contrat social (London); LOCKE, Of Civil Government; GREEN, Principles of Political Obligation (London and New York); BOSANQUET, Philosophical Theory of the State (London and New York).

Joseph Rickaby.