Francesco Zabarella

 Zabulon

 Diocese of Zacatecas

 Francesco Antonio Zaccaria

 Ludovico Zacconi

 Zacharias

 Zacharias Chrysopolitanus

 Pope St. Zachary

 János Zádori

 Zahle and Forzol

 Zakho

 Jacob Anton Zallinger zum Thurn

 Gregor Zallwein

 José Maria de Zalvidea

 Zama

 Prefecture Apostolic of the Zambesi Mission

 Diocese of Zamboanga

 Giuseppe Zamboni

 Diocese of Zamora (1)

 Diocese of Zamora (2)

 Vicariate Apostolic of Zamora

 Roman Sebastian Zängerle

 Diocese of Zante

 Francesco Zantedeschi

 Zanzibar

 Zapoteca Indians

 Archdiocese of Zara

 Zarai

 Gioseffe Zarlino

 Ulric Zasius

 Zeal

 Nicholas Tacitus Zegers

 Zela

 Karl Zell

 Ulrich Zell

 Diocese of Zengg-Modrus

 St. Zeno

 St. Zenobius

 Zenonopolis

 Zeno of Elea

 Pope St. Zephyrinus

 Zephyrium

 Zeugma

 Johann Kaspar Zeuss

 Magnoald Ziegelbauer

 Gregorius Thomas Ziegler

 Cornelius van Zierikzee

 Tommaso Maria Zigliara

 Patrick Benedict Zimmer

 Niccolò Antonio Zingarelli

 Pius Zingerle

 Zionists

 Zionites

 Diocese of Zips

 Zircz

 St. Zita

 St. Zita's Home for Friendless Women

 Zoara

 Jörgen Zoega

 Stanislaus Zolkiewski

 John Zonaras

 Zoque Indians

 Pope St. Zosimus

 Zosimus

 Zucchetto

 Diocese of Zulia

 Zululand

 Juan de Zumárraga

 Zuñi Indians

 Francisco Zurbaran

 Zurich

 Giacinto Placido Zurla

 Cistercian Abbey of Zwettl

 Ulrich Zwingli

 Ernst Friedrich Zwirner

Zeno of Elea


Greek philosopher, born at Elea, about 490 B.C. At his birthplace Xenophanes and Parmenides had established the metaphysical school of philosophy known as the Eleatic School. The chief doctrine of the school was the oneness and immutability of reality and the distrust of sense-knowledge which appears to testify to the existence of multiplicity and change. Zeno's contribution to the literature of the school consisted of a treatise, now lost, in which, according to Plato, he argued indirectly against the reality of motion and the existence of the manifold. There were, it seems, several discourses, in each of which he made a supposition, or hypothesis, and then proceeded to show the absurd consequences that would follow. This is now known as the method of indirect proof, or reductio ad absurdum, and it appears to have been used first by Zeno. Aristotle in his "Physics" has preserved the arguments by which Zeno tried to prove that motion is only apparent, or that real motion is an absurdity. The arguments are fallacious, because as Aristotle has no difficulty in showing, they are founded on on false notions of motion and space. They are, however, specious, and might well have puzzled an opponent in those days, before logic had been developed into a science. They earned for Zeno the title of "the first dialectician," and, because they seemed to be an unanswerable challenge to those who relied on the verdict of the senses, they helped to prepare the way for the skepticism of the Sophists. Besides, the method of indirect proof opened up for the sophist new possibilities in the way of contentious argument, and was very soon developed into a means of confuting an opponent. It is, consequently, the forerunner of the Eristic method, or the method of strife.

WILLIAM TURNER