Aristotle On Interpretation, Commentary by St. Thomas and Cajetan

 CONTENTS

 FOREWORD

 PREFACE

 BOOK I

 Introduction

 LESSON I

 LESSON II

 LESSON III

 LESSON IV

 LESSON V

 LESSON VI

 LESSON VII

 LESSON VIII

 LESSON IX

 LESSON X

 LESSON XI

 LESSON XII

 LESSON XIII

 LESSON XIV

 LESSON XV

 BOOK II

 LESSON I

 LESSON II

 LESSON III

 LESSON IV

 LESSON V

 LESSON VI

 LESSON VII

 LESSON VIII

 LESSON IX

 LESSON X

 LESSON XI

 LESSON XII

 LESSON XIII

 LESSON XIV

LESSON I

             16a 1 First we must establish what a name is and what a verb is; then what negation is and affirmation, and the enunciation and speech.

             4. The Philosopher begins this work with an introduction in which he points out one by one the things that are to be treated. For, since every science begins with a treatment of the principles, and the principles of composite things are their parts, one who intends to treat enunciation must begin with its parts. Therefore Aristotle begins by saying: First we must determine, i.e., define, what a name is and what a verb is. In the Greek text it is First we must posit, which signifies the same thing, for demonstrations presuppose definitions, from which they conclude, and hence definitions are rightly called "positions." This is the reason he only points out here the definitions of the things to be treated; for from definitions other things are known.

             5. It might be asked why it is necessary to treat simple things again, i.e., the name and the verb, for they were treated in the book Praedicamentorum. In answer to this we should say that simple words can be considered in three ways: first, as they signify simple intellection absolutely, which is the consideration proper to the book Praedicamentorum; secondly, according to their function as parts of the enunciation, which is the way they are considered in this book. Hence, they are treated here under the formality of the name and the verb, and under this formality they signify something with time or without time and other things of the kind that belong to the formality of words as they are components of an enunciation. Finally, simple words may be considered as they are components of a syllogistic ordering. They are treated then under the formality of terms and this Aristotle does in the book Priorum.

             6. It might be asked why he treats only the name and verb and omits the other parts of speech. The reason could be that Aristotle intends to establish rules about the simple enunciation and for this it is sufficient to consider only the parts of the enunciation that are necessary for simple speech. A simple enunciation can be formed from just a name and a verb, but it cannot be formed from other parts of speech without these. Therefore, it is sufficient to treat these two.

             On the other hand, the reason could be that names and verbs are the principal parts of speech. Pronouns, which do not name a nature but determine a person--and therefore are put in place of names--are comprehended under names. The participle--although it has similarities with the name--signifies with time and is therefore comprehended under the verb. The others are things that unite the parts of speech. They signify relations of one part to another rather than as parts of speech; as nails and other parts of this kind are not parts of a ship, but connect the parts of a ship.

             7. After he has proposed these parts [the name and the verb] as principles, Aristotle states what he principally intends to establish: . . . then what negation is and affirmation. These, too, are parts of the enunciation, not integral parts however, as are the name and verb--otherwise every enunciation would have to be formed from an affirmation and negation--but subjective parts, i.e., species. This is supposed here but will be proved later.

             8. Since enunciation is divided into categorical and hypothetical, it might be asked why he does not list these as well as affirmation and negation. In reply to this we could say that Aristotle has not added these because the hypothetical enunciation is composed of many categorical propositions and hence categorical and hypothetical only differ according to the difference of one and many.

             Or we could say--and this would be a better reason--that the hypothetical enunciation does not contain absolute truth, the knowledge of which is required in demonstration, to which this book is principally ordered; rather, it signifies something as true by supposition, which does not suffice for demonstrative sciences unless it is confirmed by the absolute truth of the simple enunciation. This is the reason Aristotle does not treat either hypothetical enunciations or syllogisms.

             He adds, and the enunciation, which is the genus of negation and affirmation; and speech, which is the genus of enunciation.

             9. If it should be asked why, besides these, he does not mention vocal sound, it is because vocal sound is something natural and therefore belongs to the consideration of natural philosophy, as is evident in II De anima and at the end of De generatio animalium. Also, since it is something natural, vocal sound is not properly the genus of speech but is presupposed for the forming of speech, as natural things are presupposed for the formation of artificial things.

             10. In this introduction, however, Aristotle seems to have inverted the order of the enunciation, for affirmation is naturally prior to negation and enunciation prior to these as a genus; and consequently, speech to enunciation. We could say in reply to this that he began to enumerate from the parts and consequently he proceeds from the parts to the whole. He puts negation, which contains division, before affirmation, which consists of composition, for the same reason: division is closer to the parts, composition closer to the whole.

             Or we could say, as some do, that he puts negation first because in those things that can be and not be, nonbeing, which negation signifies, is prior to being, which affirmation signifies.

             Aristotle, however, does not refer to the fact that one of them is placed before the other, for they are species equally dividing a genus and are therefore simultaneous according to nature.